Home         Site Map         Tutorial Material         Elements(2)         Proscribed Ops         Absolutes(1)         Absolutes(2)         Absolutes(3)         Projection         Perspective

Elements (1)


On the Elements





Mr Faulkner's treatise
probably remains representative of received projective-geometric wisdom. Just before the passage given below, the author wrote, of points, lines and planes,

We make no attempt to define these concepts, ... ”

I attempt it, however, and I query, too, some of the assumptions, as they have tacit “sub-assumptions” that do not survive scrutiny. These appear to be Euclidean notions, carried over and then misapplied.

I have underlined the statements with which I would take issue.


Many of the notions presented here are counter-intuitive, and may seem to confound “common sense”.  But common sense is more of a semi-conscious compilation of utilitarian rules-of-thumb than it is an index to fact.

For example, common sense says that parallels can't meet, but they do. The deeper problem is not whether parallels meet, but whether they exist at all.

faulkner_1
Geometric elements
do not have size
,
because none is by itself a calibrated interval [ * ].

It follows that no element is a quantity, so each must therefore be a quality.

A point, for example, is just a place, a “somewhere”. Place is its quality. A place is not an interval, so has no size - not even zero.

So a point is not “undefined”: it is defined as place.

And, I'm accordingly bound to assert that it must also follow that no element can “consist” of any other, in whatever number, because,

for one thing,

  • by definition, ‘elements’ are not composite (they are, in fact, atomic – that is to say, uncuttable.  They cannot be broken, and cannot have parts).

    To say an element consists, or is composed, of anything, is a contradiction, and a serious logical error.

    Anything that 'consists' of something else is simply not an element.
and for another thing,
  • qualities are not the quantities they would need to be in order to be summed, stacked, or aggregated (integrated) into something else—into a line, say, or a plane—as per Mr Faulkner's assumptions.
Now, the integral calculus deploys such “infinite summation” of (the orthogonal components of) “infinitesimals”. Infinitesimals are absolute, calibrated intervals that must stop just short of zero, because not even an of zeroes will sum to a non-zero value.

No doubt, if points were infinitesimals, they could be summed into lines or planes, so that these elements would ‘consist’ of them – but points are not infinitesimals.

Such “Euclideo-Newtonian” concepts are commonly, but wrongly, tacit in treatments such as Faulkner's of the elements.

Elements

The sizeless, qualitative definitions of the three, true geometric elements are as follows—
  • point is Place
  • line is Extension
  • plane is Spread



Elements(2).

Intervals

* An interval requires two elements of the same type spanned (linked) by an element of another (appropriate) type, so every simple interval always involves three elements.

Thus, for instance,

  1. two points must be linked by a line, and
  2. two lines must be linked by a point, or
  3. two lines must be linked by a plane, and
  4. two planes must be linked by a line.

In other words, projective intervals must have valid conditions of incidence.

So, for example, one point on a line, or one line in a point, does not form an interval, but two points, A and B, say, on a line, or two lines, a and b, say, in a point, make two intervals, (1) and (2), say, distinguished by sense:

← ← (2) ← A,a → (1) → B,b ← (2) ← ←

Number

Iff such intervals can be conflated with number (metricised) such that distinct intervals can be made absolutely equal (unitised/calibrated), and if such intervals can be summed, then serially contiguous intervals of type 1, in the list above, sum to distance, and those of type 2 sum to angle.

We see that the calibrated interval between two planes in a line is not an angle, because an angle is the calibrated interval between two lines in a point (type 2 above), so serially contiguous intervals of type 4 sum to what might be termed "turn" or, perhaps, "swing".

None of these conditions is native to geometry, so we rather refer to intervals in terms of what they in fact  are. We have -

  • interpunctual intervals—each having two end-points incident in a line
  • interlinear intervals—each having two end-lines incident in a plane and a point
  • interplanar intervals—each having two end-planes incident in a line
 
Home         Site Map         Tutorial Material         Elements(2)         Proscribed Ops         Absolutes(1)         Absolutes(2)         Absolutes(3)         Projection         Perspective